sábado, 26 de dezembro de 2015




Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics: originals collating, en face translation, and commented notes
     
        This research project consists mainly in a pair of related items: the first is to provide the necessary means to deliver in a critical edition a bilingual and commented translation (German-Portuguese) of the Wittgensteinian text denominated by its original editors as “Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics”; the second is to take seriously the author’s literary style rendering the text through his own concept of “physiognomy”. About the first aim, the purpose is to collect the set of manuscripts and typescrits composed on the subject between 1937 and 1944 for a work of comparison among primary and more elaborated versions, as well as later cuttings, handwritten notes on the typescripts, and lectures on the subject around the same time. About the second aim, that is to see in what sense Wittgenstein conceived his grammatical investigation on logic and mathematics as a morphology, i.e., not only taking mathematicians as inventors rather than discoverers, but as a philosophical activity guided by a double condition of authenticity and recognition. This sort of comprehension is necessary to understand the text not as a cognitive piece of discussion, which can lead to serious misunderstandings about the nature of his investigations, but as a work on oneself through writing about philosophical puzzles, or as an ethical/aesthetic philosophical performance whose objective is to leave mathematics as it is while it is liberated from a variety of philosophical confusions.


Research supported by FAPESP: Grant number 16/21147-8.

sábado, 12 de dezembro de 2015


PHILOSOPHICAL UNAWARENESS

                                              João José R. L. De Almeida
                                              joaojose@unicamp.br


The Singularity of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Physiognomy of the Text.
(in Portuguese: Editora da Unicamp, February 2016).

It always seemed intriguing to me that Wittgenstein, one of the twentieth century’s most well-known, admired and quoted philosophers, is so barely understood. What I mean is how is it possible to know exactly or even approximately what kind of philosophical activity he developed through his texts, when we have so many interpretations around: conceptual therapy, anti-philosophy, skepticism, communitarianism, mathematical naturalism, moderate intuitionism, full-blooded conventionalism, quietism, grammatical mapping of philosophical concepts? How is it possible that experts arrived to such amount of divergent philosophical views? But difficulty to fully understand his philosophy becomes really fascinating if we noticed that many people do not even realize that they did not understand him or his texts. Examples abound in this direction: Russell, Moore, Frege, Ayer, Waismann, Marcuse, Dummett, etc., just to mention some philosophers from the past.
          Contrary to the first appearances, Wittgenstein’s later texts are not properly obscure, in the plain sense of the word, or even forged in a philosophical idiom of its own. And perhaps we can also include the Tractatus, his first book, in that category. Wittgenstein’s texts are composed in a fairly normal or colloquial language, intersected with several dialogical situations where two or three voices sometimes interact. But his compositions are rather condensed and come to any conclusion. The fact is that as long as such writing style may present some challenges, it surely was not the first time in the world that such thing happened in the literature. So what is exactly the problem, and from where does it arise?
          Difficulty to understand Wittgenstein is not only a widespread and popular joke (cf. Felix Bennett in the Philosophers' Magazine cover, 2006, issue 33), it was also a concern expressed a long time ago by Maurice Drury (in Rhees, Rush (ed.). Recollections of Wittgenstein, pp. 76-85), one of his former pupils and personal friend, and something that Wittgenstein himself once acknowledged too (idem, p. 78). It is a theme from a recently published book by James Klagge (Wittgenstein in Exile, The MIT Press, 2011), and from an article published by Paul Horwich in The New York Times (“Was Wittgenstein Right?”, The New York Times, 03/03/2013).
            In this very sense, David Stern once asked a strange question: “How many Wittgensteins?” (in A. Pichler, S. Säätelä (eds.), Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and his Works, 2006, pp. 205–229). There are not only early and later Wittgensteins, apparently two quite different persons, but also a skeptical and a theoretical irreconcilables Wittgensteins, according to him.
          I’m trying to work on this intriguing problem that might be called, in the lack of a better name, philosophical unawareness. It is possible that  texts and their author are internally related, so that the best way of reading is to understand them performatively, as someone trying to fulfill two hard conditions: a condition of authenticity, fighting philosophical illusions as a care of the self, and a condition of recognition, writing about his battles for an ideal and qualified reader. All the texts, at least those written from 1929 to 1951, could also be considered as a huge package of failed attempts to publish a book. Maybe one single book, idealized in several different forms at different times, and ultimately never published. Behind and connected to that large collection of unfinished manuscripts and typescripts there is an author, someone whose stomach aches are irrelevant to the reader except by the means that he envisioned to fight them (cf. MS 136, p. 144a). Texts for the care of himself, so to say. The kind of philosophical practice remembered by Pierre Hadot in regard to Ancient Philosophy.1
            I’m publishing now (February, 2016) a book on those problems, entitled The Singularity of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Physiognomy of the Text (in Portuguese, by Editora da Unicamp). Wittgenstein’s thinking is presented there as expression of a kind of philosophical activity that has virtually no place nowadays.
___________
1. Such similarity with Ancient Philosophy was suggested to me by Yuri Zacra in personal conversation, but it is also mentioned by James Conant in “Philosophy and Biography” in: Klagge, J. (ed.). Wittgenstein: Biography & Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press, 2001, p. 20.